The Blog

Former Supreme Court Justice Souter Defends Plessy v. Ferguson

Reductio ad absurdum.

12:00 AM, Jul 14, 2010 • By ABRAM N. SHULSKY and JOHN F. BURLEIGH
Widget tooltip
Single Page Print Larger Text Smaller Text Alerts

In this latter judgment, unfortunately, Harlan was wrong.  His colleagues on the Supreme Court argued that if “the enforced separation of the two races stamps the colored race with a badge of inferiority … it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction upon it.” Strangely enough, this willingness to be blind to obvious facts is defended, in our own time, by a recently retired Supreme Court justice who recites that very centerpiece of the majority's argument without noting its tendentiousness.  Indeed, Souter is willing to accept it as reasonable, or at least as being reasonable for its time.  After all, according to Souter, for the people of the time (a mere three decades after the abolition of slavery) “the formal equality of an identical railroad car meant progress.”

At this point, the reader is no doubt wondering: what could have led Souter into such nonsense?  The answer apparently lies with the major point of Souter’s speech – his rebuttal of what he calls the “fair reading model” of constitutional jurisprudence, i.e., the view, as Souter puts it, that “deciding constitutional cases should be a straightforward exercise of reading fairly and viewing facts objectively.”

It isn’t hard to attack such a proposition.  As Souter notes, the Constitution promotes many objectives, which may conflict in certain circumstances.  New issues arise, which have to be judged in accordance with principles elaborated when those issues were unknown.  No one believes that constitutional jurisprudence can be a simple or technical matter, under any theory.

Presumably, however, constitutional jurisprudence should be guided at some level by unchanging principles.  Souter nods in this direction when he implies that judging has to find a way “to keep the constitutional promises the nation has made.”  This would seem to imply that the Constitution does indeed mean something, and that applying that something to the issues we face today is what constitutional jurisprudence is all about.

But rather than elaborate a jurisprudence based on this insight, Souter prefers to glory in indeterminacy and flux.  In his conclusion, he sees his ultimate superiority to the benighted believers in the “fair reading model” in his “belief that in an indeterminate world [he] cannot control, it is still possible to live fully in the trust that a way will be found leading through the uncertain future.  And to [him], the future of the Constitution as the Framers wrote it can be staked only upon that same trust.”

In other words, Souter can dispense with an insistence on adherence to principle because he trusts that the flow is in the right direction.  “That is how a judge lives in a state of trust…”  For that reason, he has to see the “separate but equal” doctrine of Plessy v Ferguson as a sign of racial progress, rather than as a sign of the victory of reaction that it so clearly was.  “Going with the flow” only makes sense if you regard the progress of liberty as unbroken and inevitable.  Otherwise, having some firm principles to serve as anchors isn’t such a bad idea.

Souter wants to protect a broad mandate for Supreme Court justices to make the United States the sort of country they think it should be, without having to worry overmuch about the Constitutional mooring for their exercise of this remarkable power.  However, leaving it at the “legal realist” attack on judicial opinions – that judges only dig up what they have buried – would raise the question of why unelected judges get to decide these issues in the first place.  So something more is needed, which turns out to be a watered-down relativism that relates the truth of any proposition to its time and place. (Of course, taking relativism seriously would totally undercut American veneration of the Constitution, and therewith the legitimacy of any jurisprudence based on it.)  None of these themes is articulated adequately. But mix them together and you end up with the reductio ad absurdum that is Souter’s Harvard address: Plessy was correctly decided.

John F. Burleigh is a partner in the New York law firm of Jacobs & Burleigh LLP.  Abram N. Shulsky is a senior fellow at the Hudson Institute in Washington.

Recent Blog Posts

The Weekly Standard Archives

Browse 15 Years of the Weekly Standard

Old covers